Literature/1975/Hacking

< Literature < 1975
Authors

A B C D E F G H I J K L M N
O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z &


Hacking, Ian (1975). Why Does Language Matter to Philosophy? Cambridge University Press.

Excerpts

Figures

Figure 1 (p. 165)
Experience
The Cartesian ego
Reality
Idea (mental discourse) . . . . . . . . .
:
:
:
:
v
(meanings?)

Hobbes' Leviathan (1651)
Port Royal Logic (1662)
Locke's Essay (1690)
Berkeley's Principles (1710)
. . .

Port Royal Grammaire
raisonnée et générale
(1660)
. . .
. . .
Destutt de Tracy's
Eléments d'idéologie (vol. 1, 1801) and Grammaire générale (1803)
w: Map-territory relation
See also

Comments

w: Cognitive revolution proper

Hacking argues that "public discourse has replaced mental discourse" or "sentences appear to have replaced ideas." That is, the left side or narration has replaced or trivialized the right side or ideation, or Thought on top, of the semantic triangle on the right, maybe unjustly. Along this line is Chisholm (1976) Person and Object revolting against Quine (1960) Word and Object. Figure 1 above simply details the relationship between Thought and Referent, or Person and Object. His question "why does language matter to philosophy?" rises from the fact that problematic is language in autonomy or in isolation, regardless of the cognitive, thinking or knowing, subject.

Ogden & Richards (1923) showed it up perhaps most persuasively only to be ignored. It may be that cognitive science has emerged from their thesis, but fewer and fewer acknowledge their intellectual debts to those pioneers. For example, it is simply unjust that highly celebrated Lakoff & Johnson (1980) Metaphors We Live By did not make reference to Richards (1936) The Philosophy of Rhetoric that is an extension to Ogden & Richards (1923). But, Hacking (1975) did!

What is necessary is not necessarily sufficient. Such is language, above all, contrary to the widespread common sense. It would not sufficiently reveal itself of itself so that it matters indeed so that the mind or Thought or Reference matters on top of everything else, as may be suggested by the apex of the triangle, as the ultimate mediator, as the knower of the known. So dubious is Popper's (1972) later idea of "World 3" as the place for objective knowledge without the knowing subject. So are Quine's (1960) semantic holism and Putnam's (1975) semantic externalism -- mindless of the mind! So are analytic philosophy in general and logical positivism in particular. So unavoidable was the rethinking or revolution of the world view, academic and public. Yet, it was too devastating to be accepted frankly. It had to be veiled, disguised or distorted as far as possible.

The emergence and popularity of cognitive science[1] is a hard evidence of the cognitive revolution proper, though veiled or disguised, that draws on and centers around the knowing subject and the human cognition, as opposed to the dehumanizing cognitivism such as the automated machine in autonomy or in isolation from the reality as well as mentality and morality.

In sharp contrast with the human-centered cognitive perspective, the cognitivist or computationalist perspective based on radical reductionism is not really to have to do with, but to defeat or do without, the mind or human cognition proper, to replace dearer and dearer manpower with cheaper and cheaper computer power for profit-making. The so-called cognitive revolution, if anything similar, "since 1956" must have been a cognitivist revolution giving rise to dehumanizing artificial intelligence until it came across the AI winter, such as since the late 1970s.

Chomsky's universal grammar would be another cognitivist dehumanizing case, hence a misleading claim, if any, for the cognitive revolution. Any grammar should be confined within the necessary but insufficient condition of language in isolation from the situation out there and the ideation in here. Percy (1975) proudly dubbed such a lingual irreducibility the "delta factor" that is still another new wording for the truly holist trinity of meaning.

Such is also the case with the dictionary. In this regard, Fillmore (1976) argues for frame semantics that attempts to take advantage of both the dictionary and the encyclopedia coupled so as to help better understand the meaning of words beyond the dictionary definition.

Wikimedia

Chronology

Comments

    Notes

    1. The earliest claim for cognitive science includes: Johnson-Laird, Philip N. & Peter Cathcart Wason eds. (1977). Thinking: Readings in Cognitive Science. Cambridge University Press. [+]
    1900s ^
    '00 '01 '02 '03 '04 '05 '06 '07 '08 '09
    '10 '11 '12 '13 '14 '15 '16 '17 '18 '19
    '20 '21 '22 '23 '24 '25 '26 '27 '28 '29
    '30 '31 '32 '33 '34 '35 '36 '37 '38 '39
    '40 '41 '42 '43 '44 '45 '46 '47 '48 '49
    '50 '51 '52 '53 '54 '55 '56 '57 '58 '59
    '60 '61 '62 '63 '64 '65 '66 '67 '68 '69
    '70 '71 '72 '73 '74 '75 '76 '77 '78 '79
    '80 '81 '82 '83 '84 '85 '86 '87 '88 '89
    '90 '91 '92 '93 '94 '95 '96 '97 '98 '99
    2000s
    '00 '01 '02 '03 '04 '05 '06 '07 '08 '09
    '10 '11 '12 '13 '14 '15 '16 '17 '18 '19
    1900s category ^
    '00 '01 '02 '03 '04 '05 '06 '07 '08 '09
    '10 '11 '12 '13 '14 '15 '16 '17 '18 '19
    '20 '21 '22 '23 '24 '25 '26 '27 '28 '29
    '30 '31 '32 '33 '34 '35 '36 '37 '38 '39
    '40 '41 '42 '43 '44 '45 '46 '47 '48 '49
    '50 '51 '52 '53 '54 '55 '56 '57 '58 '59
    '60 '61 '62 '63 '64 '65 '66 '67 '68 '69
    '70 '71 '72 '73 '74 '75 '76 '77 '78 '79
    '80 '81 '82 '83 '84 '85 '86 '87 '88 '89
    '90 '91 '92 '93 '94 '95 '96 '97 '98 '99
    2000s category
    '00 '01 '02 '03 '04 '05 '06 '07 '08 '09
    '10 '11 '12 '13 '14 '15 '16 '17 '18 '19
    1900s works ad hoc
    '00 '01 '02 '03 '04 '05 '06 '07 '08 '09
    '10 '11 '12 '13 '14 '15 '16 '17 '18 '19
    '20 '21 '22 '23 '24 '25 '26 '27 '28 '29
    '30 '31 '32 '33 '34 '35 '36 '37 '38 '39
    '40 '41 '42 '43 '44 '45 '46 '47 '48 '49
    '50 '51 '52 '53 '54 '55 '56 '57 '58 '59
    '60 '61 '62 '63 '64 '65 '66 '67 '68 '69
    '70 '71 '72 '73 '74 '75 '76 '77 '78 '79
    '80 '81 '82 '83 '84 '85 '86 '87 '88 '89
    '90 '91 '92 '93 '94 '95 '96 '97 '98 '99
    2000s works
    '00 '01 '02 '03 '04 '05 '06 '07 '08 '09
    '10 '11 '12 '13 '14 '15 '16 '17 '18 '19
    1900s books cat. ^
    '00 '01 '02 '03 '04 '05 '06 '07 '08 '09
    '10 '11 '12 '13 '14 '15 '16 '17 '18 '19
    '20 '21 '22 '23 '24 '25 '26 '27 '28 '29
    '30 '31 '32 '33 '34 '35 '36 '37 '38 '39
    '40 '41 '42 '43 '44 '45 '46 '47 '48 '49
    '50 '51 '52 '53 '54 '55 '56 '57 '58 '59
    '60 '61 '62 '63 '64 '65 '66 '67 '68 '69
    '70 '71 '72 '73 '74 '75 '76 '77 '78 '79
    '80 '81 '82 '83 '84 '85 '86 '87 '88 '89
    '90 '91 '92 '93 '94 '95 '96 '97 '98 '99
    2000s books category
    '00 '01 '02 '03 '04 '05 '06 '07 '08 '09
    '10 '11 '12 '13 '14 '15 '16 '17 '18 '19
    http://books.google.com/advanced_book_search
    The shade of the bar looks invariant in isolation but variant in context, in (favor of) sharp contrast with the color gradient background, hence an innate illusion we have to reasonably interpret and overcome as well as the mirage. Such variance appearing seasonably from context to context may not only be the case with our vision but worldview in general in practice indeed, whether a priori or a posteriori. Perhaps no worldview from nowhere, without any point of view or prejudice at all!

    Ogden & Richards (1923) said, "All experience ... is either enjoyed or interpreted ... or both, and very little of it escapes some degree of interpretation."

    H. G. Wells (1938) said, "The human individual is born now to live in a society for which his fundamental instincts are altogether inadequate."

    This article is issued from Wikiversity - version of the Tuesday, September 30, 2014. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.